Kant, Doyle, and the Democratic Peace Thesis: A Postcolonial Critique

0
13

Immanuel Kant’s work on worldwide politics has been given renewed emphasis by Michael W. Doyle in his two-part article Kant, Liberal Legacies, and International Affairs (1983). The article establishes continuity between the Kantian undertaking and trendy liberal thought in Worldwide Relations (IR); particularly, Doyle finds his democratic peace thesis — the truth that liberal democracies don’t wage warfare in opposition to each other — to be in step with Kant’s three Definitive Articles for perpetual peace. On nearer inspection, nevertheless, the similarities between the 2 theories fades. This essay adopts a crucial, postcolonial outlook to problem Democratic Peace Concept (DPT) on two grounds: first, to exhibit that it provides, at finest, a really a lot distorted interpretation of Kant’s authentic predicaments; second, to denounce the intolerant, imperialist character produced by such a distortion. DPT’s theoretical profile will show a lot nearer to the liberalism of John Stuart Mill; in different phrases, to a broadly racist, Eurocentric perspective. In the end, this essay argues that DPT fails to include a Kantian philosophy to supply an efficient and coherent idea of progress; its imperialist underpinnings impede progress if not actively contribute to the perpetuation of worldwide battle.

The essay is split into 4 sections. Within the first part, I introduce the principle theoretical considerations of postcolonial idea. This can permit for a crucial method to the Eurocentric character of the worldwide order and, particularly, to the fashionable liberal agenda. I additionally specify what is supposed by the in any other case unfastened time period “imperialism” by formulating three standards. Within the second part, I summarise essentially the most related rules of DPT. Within the course of, I exhibit that DPT matches the three standards of imperialism. Successively, I revise Kant’s three Definitive Articles for perpetual peace within the third part. The comparability with DPT will reveal that not solely does it misrepresent Kant’s concepts, it additionally works in a route that’s reverse to them. Lastly, having decoupled Kant and DPT, I set up a connection between the latter and the liberalism of John Stuart Mill. This analytical course of is meant to stimulate trendy liberal thinkers usually, and DPT theorists particularly, to interact in self-criticism and to develop into far more aware of the goal of progress.

Postcolonialism and the Fashionable Liberal Agenda in Worldwide Relations

Postcolonial idea reveals the Eurocentric character of IR in two essential methods. First, it engages with historical past, which is in any other case too typically uncared for within the self-discipline. Particularly, it investigates the historic basis of the fashionable worldwide order. The mainstream narrative on this respect means that it developed inside Europe to then unfold to the opposite continents. The European system, formalised by the Westphalia settlement, progressively expanded outwards; the Industrial Revolution empowered Europeans with financial and technological superiority vis-à-vis non-Europeans, which was readily employed to propagandise the European capitalist mannequin overseas. In the end, the Europeans introduced progress and modernity to the international peoples (Seth, 2011: 169-170). For sure, this narrative is problematic. To start with, it diminishes the horrors of the European growth, akin to bloody conquests, genocides, exploitation and oppression, as secondary developments inside a much wider image. Postcolonialism argues that this isn’t the case; relatively, such developments have been central to the inspiration of the fashionable worldwide order. As an illustration, one in every of its defining properties, capitalism, unlikely emerged solely from inter-European commerce. Rather more believable is that the conquest of the Americas – thus the importation of recent uncooked supplies – and the transatlantic slave commerce enabled it to emerge within the first place (Seth, 2011: 171-174). It’s crucial to understand the significance of those international interconnections, or else the fashionable worldwide order will proceed to be related to “a colonial anthropology wherein a legendary righteous West poses as trainer for others” (Grovogui, 2013: 251).

The second means wherein postcolonial idea reveals the Eurocentric character of IR is by questioning the character of the procedural guidelines of interplay amongst states. Because the world was turning into more and more globalised within the second half of the nineteenth century, it was important to control the interactions amongst free peoples within the public area. The answer rested within the distinction between “substance” and “process”. The brand new worldwide order needed to be inclusive, relatively than unique: it will keep cultural variety and set up a horizontal relationship amongst states. On the similar time, it will produce value-free (procedural) norms, devoid of any content material or particularity, to control interactions. Liberalism emerged because the triumphant face of this new worldwide order (Seth, 2011: 174-176). The difficulty is quickly established: “removed from being impartial…the procedural norms adopted presupposed, and thus favoured, Christian values over different values, males over girls and so forth” (Seth, 2011: 176). As an illustration, as critics level out, worldwide regulation emerged in Europe to then broaden outwardly. Equally, norms and practices of diplomacy have been established in Europe however have been prolonged to the remainder of the world nonetheless. It is vitally laborious to imagine that these procedural norms, that are so linked to their European origins, are devoid of any cultural particularity. Nor it’s acceptable to imagine that, solely as a result of the remainder of the world has the truth is largely complied with them, such norms may be considered actually common (Seth, 2011: 177).

These two premises permit for a crucial method to trendy liberalism in IR. We wish to ask ourselves: has the West any proper to pose as trainer for others? Are Western values actually common and, if not, ought to they be? The post-1989 period begs these questions; it’s the truth is outlined by a resurgence of Western paternalism, as the top of the Chilly Warfare introduced the “alternative for universalizing Western civilization in order to ‘assist and rescue’ Japanese societies” (Hobson, 2012: 286). It is a interval marked by a powerful diploma of optimism and Western triumphalism, characterised by the widespread assumption that the universalisation of Western civilisation and norms is a progressive good that can profit all peoples. Fashionable liberals are cautious to characterise the post-1989 period as a definite one within the historical past of liberal thought, the place new progressive and egalitarian values akin to democracy, multiculturalism and human rights have taken on the liberal agenda. They wish to keep away from any affiliation with the post-1830 period of manifest Eurocentric liberal worldwide thought, which is “reimagined as extra racially illiberal and imperialist than it was in order that the post-1989 period may be portrayed as extra culturally tolerant and anti-imperialist than it’s” (Hobson, 2012: 285-286). Satirically, as Hobson (2012: 286) observes, trendy liberal thought in IR “has develop into presumably extra imperialist since 1989 than it was within the nineteenth century”. This essay will exhibit that that is the case.

First, nevertheless, it’s essential to outline what makes a sure political thought “imperialist”. I borrow Jahn’s (2005: 177-178) characterisation, which defines “imperialist” any political thought that entails three parts: (1) a justification for interventions geared toward altering the cultural, political and financial buildings of a goal state; (2) a readiness to intervene even when the consent of the goal society is missing; (3) a principled approval of using navy pressure to result in change. The subsequent part will exhibit that DPT matches all three of those standards.

Democratic Peace Concept and Imperialism

A quick abstract of DPT is important to grasp why it matches the three standards of imperialism. Doyle (1983a: 206-212; see additionally Jahn, 2005: 180-181) primarily defines liberal states by the liberty and equality of residents, a consultant authorities and personal property. Statistically, he finds that such states “have but to interact in warfare with each other”, whereas they do at instances go to warfare in opposition to non-liberal states (Doyle, 1983a: 213). For Doyle (1983a: 225-232), Kant’s Perpetual Peace “provides the perfect steerage” to grasp this empirical discovering. As a result of in liberal states residents bear the burden of warfare, they’re incentivised to keep away from it; thus republics are typically inclined towards warning, in keeping with Kant’s First Definitive Article. These states set up mutual belief by way of the sharing of norms and establishments, which permits for peaceable battle resolutions. A “separate peace” is thus established amongst liberal states, in conformity with Kant’s Federation of Free States, discovered within the Second Definitive Article. The “spirit of commerce”, i.e. financial interdependence, strengthens this separate peace, as postulated within the Third Definitive Article.

The identical rules that account for liberal peace clarify the recurrence of warfare between liberal and non-liberal states. As a result of they don’t share the identical norms and establishments, non-liberal states can’t be trusted; relatively, they’re checked out with suspicion and anticipated to be aggressive. As Doyle (1986: 1162) explains, in relation to non-liberal states, “liberal states haven’t escaped from the insecurity attributable to anarchy on the earth political system thought of as an entire”. World peace thus turns into a matter of selling liberal rules overseas: non-liberal states should be transformed to liberalism to develop into a part of the ever-expanding liberal “separate peace” (Doyle, 1983b: 325-326, 330-331; Jahn, 2005: 181; Russett, 2013: 101). In Russett’s (2013: 111) phrases: “selling democracy…provides the potential of strengthening present peaceable relations and increasing their scope to many of the world”. Non-liberal states, alternatively, haven’t any proper to non-interference as they “don’t authentically signify the rights of people” (Doyle, 1986: 1162). Crucially, then, whereas liberal states respect norms of sovereignty and non-intervention amongst themselves, they don’t seem to be keen to ensure the identical rights to the non-liberal ones. The latter are given what Hobson (2012: 289) refers to as a “conditional standing” based mostly on the diploma to which they respect human rights; as he additionally stresses, conditional sovereignty is a crucial pre-requisite for Western neo-imperialist interventions. Accordingly, Cavallar (2001: 241) is sceptical concerning the liberal justification for interventions in opposition to non-liberal states. What number of instances, he appears to be asking, have been liberal international insurance policies pushed by cultural prejudices and ideological convictions, versus the noble respect for human rights? In spite of everything, DPT implies that interventionism ought to finally result in the “teleological” evolution of non-Western societies into the idealised Western liberal societies (Hobson, 2012: 288).

One other essential query involves the fore: is the consent of the goal society required for the promotion of liberalism overseas? Though Doyle doesn’t explicitly deal with this challenge, Jahn (2005: 181-182) provides a persuasive reply. Since, for Doyle, liberal constitutions derive their legitimacy from consent, the shortage of consent correct of non-liberal states routinely interprets into an absence of legitimacy. This development implies that the populations of non-liberal states would, in precept, embrace a liberal structure, however that they’re prevented from doing so by the use of autocratic oppression, non-liberal cultural traditions, or an absence of publicity to some great benefits of liberal life. Consent, then, will not be a requisite for liberal intervention.

Lastly, liberal interventionism towards non-liberal states rests largely on a proper rejection of using navy pressure. Doyle (1983b: 335) warns his readers of the counterproductive results that the deployment of the navy overseas might need on home safety; paradoxically, he additionally demonstrates that liberal states have recurred to navy pressure a number of instances prior to now. Russett (2013: 111), too, asserts that liberal states ought to promote democracy “however hardly ever imposing it by pressure, after which solely in response to aggression”. But, the exclusion of using pressure is dictated by prudence. Doyle doesn’t formulate any normative constraint on using pressure, any principled categorical rejection. Due to this fact, despite the fact that liberals should not keen about it, using navy pressure stays an out there possibility that can’t be excluded a priori (Jahn, 2005: 182).

Evidently, then, DPT matches all three of the factors that make a political thought imperialist. Doyle works out a technique to justify interventions towards non-liberal states with out the consent of the goal society and leaving open the likelihood for using navy pressure. He claims this to be in step with the Kantian undertaking for perpetual peace, however is it actually?

The Kantian Mission for Perpetual Peace and Democratic Peace Concept

Kant lays out three Definitive Articles in his masterwork Perpetual Peace. In a nutshell, the Articles prescribe republicanism, federalism and cosmopolitanism: these are the weather that, coordinated amongst themselves, would result in progress and perpetual peace. As we’ve seen, Doyle claims continuity between these Articles and his democratic peace thesis. Allow us to now set up if that is actually the case by every Article in higher element.

First Definitive Article

The First Definitive Article establishes that “the Civil Structure of Each State shall be Republican” (Kant, 1991b [1795]: 99). Kant intends the republican structure to ensure freedom, equality and justice to all residents by the use of “a separation of the chief and legislative and … a point of illustration” (Hurrell, 1990: 195; Kant, 1991b [1795]: 99-102). On a practical degree, a republican structure makes the prospect of warfare much less possible, because the residents, who’re themselves self-legislators, would have “nice hesitation in embarking on so harmful an enterprise” (Kant, 1991b [1795]: 100). Kant presupposes the need for happiness in all human beings; because of this republican residents, who would themselves pay the prices, both in type of loss of life, damage or financial wrestle, are likely to keep away from the miseries of warfare. Two {qualifications} observe.

First, we should assume that Kant intends republican residents to keep away from all wars, whatever the nature of the warfare or the regime sort of the opponent (Cavallar, 2001: 233). Second, we should assume that in a very republican state, to ensure that it to be practical to the goal of peace, all residents should bear the burden of warfare. Doyle’s liberal states hardly show such traits. As we’ve seen, Doyle argues that liberal states don’t wage warfare in opposition to one another, however that they do typically wage warfare in opposition to non-liberal states. Furthermore, in trendy democracies not all residents bear the burden of warfare. Often solely a small part of the inhabitants – younger males – will get concerned in warfare. Many voters even profit from warfare. Moreover, the empirical report is loads of instances the place liberal democracies supported warfare, most notoriously in World Warfare I. Since all republican residents should bear the prices of warfare, all of them ought to logically be allowed to vote by way of common suffrage. Doyle is as an alternative happy with 30% male suffrage, thus he enlists the French Republic of 1790-1795 and the post-1776 United States as liberal democracies (Cavallar, 2001: 237-238).

Allow us to make one other essential consideration. Kant clearly anticipated republican constitutions to come up out of an inner political course of. The inhabitants would channel the “unsocial sociability” correct of all people to embrace the civil structure that, when confronted with all the opposite choices, is essentially the most applicable to allow the fullest ethical growth, in accordance with nature’s design (Kant, 1991a [1784]: 44-47). Put merely, the republican structure rests on the consent of the inhabitants. As Jahn (2005: 189) observes, Kant didn’t imagine that the republican structure might be established by exterior interference. He’s very specific about non-intervention within the Fifth Preliminary Article, the place he claims that “no state shall forcibly intervene within the structure and authorities of one other state” (Kant, 1991b [1795]: 96). This Article is of the strictest type, to be revered below all circumstances; a “precept of equality” should regulate worldwide behaviour. Whereas critics have interpreted Kant as if he justifies intervention in instances of totalitarian coup d’états or grave disrespect of human rights, the textual proof runs in the wrong way (Cavallar, 2001: 240-242; Hurrell, 1990: 200). Therefore, on nearer inspection, Doyle’s assertions disintegrate: liberal democracies don’t correspond to Kant’s republics, nor are they allowed to intervene in opposition to non-liberal states.

Second Definitive Article

The Second Definitive Article asserts that “the Proper of Nations shall be based mostly on a Federation of Free [my emphasis] States” (Kant, 1991b [1795]: 102). Doyle clearly equates the phrase “free” with the republican structure. So, his argument runs, a liberal home structure is a requisite for membership in Kant’s confederation. In spite of everything, he solely admits liberal states in what he calls the “pacific union”. Did Kant actually imply the pacific confederation to be an unique one? Two concerns disprove it. First, as MacMillan (2006: 62) factors out, Kant employs the phrase “free” to seek advice from standing relatively than type. That’s, freedom corresponds to independence and sovereignty relatively than to a particular regime sort. Additional, freedom is simply one of many three rules correct of a republican structure (the opposite two are the dependency of all residents on a standard laws and authorized equality), due to this fact they can’t be logically synonymous. Second, Kant by no means specifies that non-liberal states shall be excluded from the pacific confederation. True, he refers to a “highly effective and enlightened” republic that would offer the “point of interest for federal affiliation amongst different states” (Kant, 1991b [1795]: 104), but these “different states” should not additionally explicitly anticipated to be republican (Cavallar, 2001: 244; MacMillan, 2006: 63).

Whereas Kant appears to take into account a pact of mutual non-aggression, a collective safety settlement open to all states no matter regime sort, properly conscious that worldwide anarchy jeopardises peace and ethical growth, Doyle predicates an unique membership of liberal states, a “separate peace” (Hurrell, 1990: 183-184). This suggests a powerful division between liberal and non-liberal states, which finally ends in the perpetuation of the safety dilemma. As Hurrell (1990: 193) readily notices, “Except such a federation is ready to develop into actually common, its impact is merely to rearrange the items throughout the worldwide anarchy, relatively than overcome that anarchy”. Doyle’s argument, then, will not be in step with Kant’s: one is making an attempt to beat the worldwide anarchy, the opposite is merely reconfiguring the safety dilemma.

Third Definitive Article

The Third Definitive Article states that “Cosmopolitan Proper shall be restricted to Situations of Common Hospitality” (Kant, 1991b [1795]: 105). Kant considers the transnational boundaries to peace and establishes {that a} refusal of interplay should not result in the loss of life of the applicant. Whereas he believes within the pacifying potential of commerce, he’s crucial of the industrial states of his time, particularly Britain and the Netherlands, the pursuits of that are seen as a supply of imperialism that results in injustice and the perpetuation of warfare (Kant, 1991b [1795]: 105-108). The imperialist character of such industrial states spurs from the assumed “proper to commerce”, imposed on others. Kant, nevertheless, is definitely limiting that very proper, since cosmopolitan regulation solely permits for the correct to hospitality and presumes that commerce and different types of interplay are ethical provided that “entered into voluntarily by all events” (Jahn, 2005: 192, 191-192).

Doyle, like many different liberals in IR, obscures Kant’s thought of cosmopolitan proper by associating it with liberal financial idea. He insists {that a} free market economic system is a defining characteristic of liberal democracies, and that financial interdependence is among the explanations for why liberal states don’t wage warfare in opposition to one another. Really, nevertheless, Kant decouples commerce from hospitality and doesn’t regard it as both a vital or a ample factor for perpetual peace. In spite of everything, his Third and Fourth Preliminary Articles are fairly at odds with liberal financial rules (Simpson, 2019: 115, 119). Nonetheless, DPT and different liberal theories of IR insist on selling the opening of recent markets overseas. They assist bilateral and multilateral agreements, such because the World Commerce Organisation and the Worldwide Financial Fund, which, regardless of being formally voluntary, may be seen as being really “imposed” given the determined financial dependence of many creating states (Jahn, 2005: 192). As Hobson (2012: 290-291) suggests, globalisation is in the present day a chance for liberal states to assimilate non-liberal societies and universalise the liberal financial mannequin. Doyle embraces this chance emphasising commerce over hospitality, clearly ignoring Kant’s considerations on imperialism.

Mill’s Legacies in Democratic Peace Concept

The earlier part has demonstrated that DPT can not declare continuity with the Kantian undertaking for perpetual peace. I now proceed to argue that DPT is definitely far more nearer to the liberalism of John Stuart Mill (Jahn, 2005: 194-198).

Mill’s political thought is explicitly pushed by racism and offers a justification for imperialism. To start with, Mill identifies 4 phases of growth in historical past: savagery, slavery, barbarism and trendy civilisation. The latter is outlined by personal property and widespread intelligence; savages, he explains, lack these parts to represent the polar opposites of civilised folks (Mill, 1977a [1836]: 120-122). Crucially, for Mill, the stage of growth is linked to the type of authorities, the very best of which is Britain’s consultant authorities: “As … [peoples] vary decrease and decrease in growth, that type of authorities shall be, typically talking, much less appropriate to them” (Mill, 1977b [1861]: 413). Equally, Doyle explicitly defines liberal democracy as the perfect type of authorities; he too establishes a separation, between liberal and non-liberal states, which rests on regime sort.

Mill’s separation of contemporary civilization from the opposite phases of growth begs two concerns. First, that not all states profit from equal rights. The proper to sovereignty is allotted relying on the diploma to which a state reciprocates norms of worldwide behaviour. Barbarians are clearly deemed incapable of such a factor; due to this fact, Mill explains, they “haven’t any rights as a nation, besides a proper to such therapy as might, on the earliest potential interval, match them for turning into one” (Mill, 2006 [1859]: 259). Doyle, too, is keen to recognise one other state’s rights to sovereignty and non-intervention based mostly on the diploma to which it complies with worldwide regulation. As we’ve seen, trendy liberals in IR concede a “conditional standing” to the non-liberal ones based mostly, above all, on the diploma to which they respect human rights (Hobson, 2012: 288-290).

Second, Mill believes that barbarous states would profit from intervention; in his phrases: “nations that are nonetheless barbarous haven’t received past the interval throughout which it’s more likely to be for his or her profit that they need to be conquered and held in subjection by foreigners” (Mill, 2006 [1859]: 259). This mirrors fairly properly Doyle’s thought. For him, intervention is a method to deliver democracy to a international society and, most significantly, to enlarge the liberal “separate peace”. As identified above, trendy liberals assume that the goal society would, in precept, embrace liberal beliefs, due to this fact we are able to consider interventions as a technique to velocity up the method of democratisation for the good thing about the international peoples. Given these concerns, it’s a lot simpler to determine parallels between Mill and DPT than it’s to see continuity between Kant and the latter.

Conclusion

A postcolonial outlook has proved helpful to establish the imperialist parts of DPT. Doyle’s idea, as we’ve seen, diverges considerably from Kant’s to justify interventions in non-liberal states even when the consent of the native inhabitants is missing and presumably with using navy pressure. The postcolonial concerns on the foundations and workings of the fashionable worldwide order are strengthened by DPT, which does in spite of everything conceive the West as an ethical trainer for others and the universalisation of Western civilisation and norms as a progressive good for all.

This essay is supposed to stimulate trendy liberals in IR to interact in self-criticism. Evidently, a failure on the a part of DPT to include Kant to supply a coherent and efficient idea of progress – and the shut affiliation with Mill’s imperialist political thought – is means too problematic. Kant invitations his readers to embrace the prospect of progress advocating the abolition of all wars and the decision of the issue of worldwide anarchy. By misinterpreting Kant’s message, Doyle really works in the wrong way. He doesn’t condemn all wars, nor using navy pressure; most significantly, he rearranges the safety dilemma, leaving non-liberal states below the fixed risk of warfare. This generates, by his personal admission, “super struggling” (Doyle, 1986: 1163). As interventionism is conceived as a denial of self-determinism, the result’s radicalisation, intolerance and fragile safety (Jahn, 2007: 89). Updated, due to this fact, DPT proves inconsistent with the goal of progress. Not solely do its imperialist underpinnings impede progress, in addition they actively contribute to the perpetuation of warfare. Crucially, trendy liberalism in IR should resign its imperialist foundations if it needs to realize progress in keeping with Kant’s hopes.

Reference Listing

Cavallar, Georg (2001) “Kantian Views on Democratic Peace: Alternate options to Doyle”, Overview of Worldwide Research 27(2): 229-248.

Doyle, Michael W. (1983a) “Kant, Liberal Legacies and International Affairs”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 12(3): 205-235.

Doyle, Michael W. (1983b) “Kant, Liberal Legacies and International Affairs, Half 2”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 12(4): 323-353.

Doyle, Michael W. (1986) “Liberalism and World Politics”, The American Political Science Overview 80(4): 1151-1169.

Grovogui, Siva N. (2013) “Postcolonialism”, in Dunne, Tim, Kurki, Milja and Smith, Steve (eds.) Worldwide Relations Theories: Self-discipline and Range, 3rd version (Oxford: Oxford College Press), 247-265.

Hobson, John M. (2012) The Eurocentric Conception of World Politics: Western Worldwide Concept, 1760-2010, 1st version (Cambridge: Cambridge College Press).

Hurrell, Andrew (1990) “Kant and the Kantian Paradigm in Worldwide Relations”, Overview of Worldwide Research 16(3): 183-205.

Jahn, Beate (2005) “Kant, Mill, and Intolerant Legacies in Worldwide Affairs”, Worldwide Group 59(1): 177-207.  

Jahn, Beate (2007) “The Tragedy of Liberal Diplomacy: Democratization, Intervention, Statebuilding (Half I)”, Journal of Intervention and Statebuilding 1(1): 87-106.

Kant, Immanuel (1991a [1784]) “Thought for a Common Historical past with a Cosmopolitan Goal”, in Reiss, Hans (ed.) Kant: Political Writings, 2nd version (Cambridge: Cambridge College Press), 41-53.

Kant, Immanuel (1991b [1795]) “Perpetual Peace”, in Reiss, Hans (ed.) Kant: Political Writings, 2nd version(Cambridge: Cambridge College Press), 93-115.

MacMillan, John (2006) “Immanuel Kant and the democratic peace”, in Jahn, Beate (ed.) Classical Concept in Worldwide Relations, 1st version (Cambridge: Cambridge College Press), 52-73.

Mill, John Stuart (1977a [1836]) “Civilization”, in Robson, John M. (ed.) The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Vol. 18: Essays on Politics and Society Half I, 1st version(Toronto: College of Toronto Press), 117-148.

Mill, John Stuart (1977b [1861]) “Concerns on Consultant Authorities”, in Robson, John M. (ed.) The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Vol. 19: Essays on Politics and Society Half II, 1st version(Toronto: College of Toronto Press), 371-578.

Mill, John Stuart (2006 [1859]) “A Few Phrases on Non-Intervention”, New England Overview (1990-) 27(3): 252-264.

Russett, Bruce (2013) “Liberalism”, in Dunne, Tim, Kurki, Milja and Smith, Steve (eds.) Worldwide Relations Theories: Self-discipline and Range, 3rd version (Oxford: Oxford College Press), 94-113.

Seth, Sanjay (2011) “Postcolonial Concept and the Critique of Worldwide Relations”, Millennium: Journal of Worldwide Research 40: 167-183.

Simpson, Sid (2019) “Making liberal use of Kant? Democratic peace idea and Perpetual Peace”, Worldwide Relations 33(1): 109-128.

Additional Studying on E-Worldwide Relations